Zombies and consciousness /

Saved in:
Bibliographic Details
Author / Creator:Kirk, Robert, 1933-
Imprint:Oxford : Clarendon Press ; New York : Oxford University Press, 2005.
Description:xii, 235 p. ; 24 cm.
Language:English
Subject:
Format: E-Resource Print Book
URL for this record:http://pi.lib.uchicago.edu/1001/cat/bib/5823445
Hidden Bibliographic Details
ISBN:0199285489 (alk. paper)
Notes:Includes bibliographical references (p. [219]-225) and index.
Also available on the Internet to subscribing institutions.
Standard no.:9780199285488
Table of Contents:
  • 1. Introduction
  • 1.1. Two kinds of ignorance about prawns
  • 1.2. The zombie idea
  • 1.3. Outline
  • 2. Zombies and Minimal Physicalism
  • 2.1. Causal closure and epiphenomenalism
  • 2.2. Redescription and strict implication
  • 2.3. More about physicalism and strict implication
  • 2.4. A posteriori necessity and physicalism
  • 2.5. Psychological and physical explicability
  • 2.6. Seeing whether descriptions fit reality, versus looking for analytic connections
  • 2.7. Conclusion
  • 3. The Case for Zombies
  • 3.1. Kinds of zombies
  • 3.2. Two old arguments
  • 3.3. The argument from conceivability
  • 3.4. Does conceivability entail possibility?
  • 3.5. Chalmers's arguments for conceivability
  • 3.6. The 'knowledge argument'
  • 3.7. The argument 'from the absence of analysis'
  • 3.8. Conclusion
  • 4. Zapping the Zombie Idea
  • 4.1. Conflict among intuitions
  • 4.2. The jacket fallacy
  • 4.3. The e-qualia story
  • 4.4. E-qualia, causation, and cognitive processing
  • 4.5. Are e-qualia alone enough for epistemic intimacy?
  • 4.6. My zombie twin's sole-pictures
  • 4.7. The e-qualia story is not conceivable
  • 4.8. If zombies were conceivable, the e-qualia story would be conceivable
  • 4.9. Objections
  • 4.10. Sole-pictures versus soul-pictures
  • 4.11. Corollaries
  • 4.12. Looking ahead
  • 5. What Has To Be Done
  • 5.1. Varieties of consciousness
  • 5.2. Nagel's two kinds of concepts
  • 5.3. Three problems: (i) What is it like? (ii) Is it like anything? (iii) What is it?
  • 5.4. Do we have to get a priori from physical facts to what it is like?
  • 5.5. Must there be a third type of event?
  • 5.6. Block's two concepts of consciousness
  • 5.7. Do we need a new science?
  • 5.8. Does this project involve 'conceptual analysis'? Does it involve armchair science?
  • 5.9. More on the what-is-it problem
  • 5.10. The moderate realism of everyday psychology
  • 5.11. Summary
  • 6. Deciders
  • 6.1. What really matters?
  • 6.2. Perception and control
  • 6.3. Pure reflex systems
  • 6.4. Pure reflex systems with acquired stimuli
  • 6.5. Built-in triggered reflex systems
  • 6.6. Triggered reflex systems with acquired conditions
  • 6.7. Monitoring and controlling the responses
  • 6.8. Deciders
  • 6.9. Unity of the basic package
  • 6.10. The basic package and perception
  • 6.11. Usefulness of the basic package idea
  • 7. Decision, Control, and Integration
  • 7.1. Simple organisms
  • 7.2. 'Bees can think say scientists'
  • 7.3. Interpretation, assessment, and decision-making by the whole organism
  • 7.4. The human embryo, foetus, and neonate
  • 7.5. The artificial giant
  • 7.6. Block's machines
  • 7.7. The machine-table robot
  • 7.8. Untypical deciders
  • 7.9. Other robots
  • 7.10. An indeterminate case
  • 7.11. Some lessons
  • 7.12. Basicness of the basic package
  • 8. De-sophisticating the Framework
  • 8.1. The objection
  • 8.2. The 'concept-exercising and reasoning system'
  • 8.3. Concept possession is not all-or-nothing
  • 8.4. More on having concepts
  • 8.5. Representation
  • 8.6. Concepts and theories
  • 8.7. Mistaken beliefs and 'public norms'
  • 8.8. The basic package and rationality
  • 8.9. Deciders might be subjects of experience without being persons
  • 8.10. The basic package and 'non-conceptual content'
  • 8.11. The contents of deciders' informational states
  • 8.12. Conclusion
  • 9. Direct Activity
  • 9.1. The basic package, control, and consciousness
  • 9.2. Why the basic package seems insufficient for perceptual consciousness
  • 9.3. The Evans-Type model
  • 9.4. Concepts and the acquisition of information
  • 9.5. Registration and conceptualization
  • 9.6. Two points about information and registration
  • 9.7. Directly active perceptual information: instantaneity and priority
  • 9.8. A holistic approach to direct activity
  • 9.9. Can we really understand direct activity holistically and not in terms of 'poisedness'?
  • 9.10. Significance of direct activity
  • 9.11. Degrees of consciousness and the richness of perceptual information
  • 9.12. Phenomenal consciousness in general
  • 9.13. Why is it like this?
  • 9.14. Conclusion
  • 10. Gap? What Gap?
  • 10.1. Extending the sole-pictures argument
  • 10.2. Zoë
  • 10.3. Being able to tell the difference
  • 10.4. Zoë's abilities
  • 10.5. Provisional conclusions
  • 10.6. Some misconceptions
  • 10.7. What this account does
  • 10.8. Blindsight
  • 10.9. Automatism
  • 10.10. General objections to functionalist accounts
  • 10.11. The 'explanatory gap'
  • 10.12. Awareness of experiences
  • 10.13. Carruthers's critique
  • 10.14. 'Worldly-subjectivity', 'mental-state subjectivity', and higher-order thought
  • 10.15. More objections
  • 10.16. Why there will always seem to be a gap
  • 11. Survival of the Fittest
  • 11.1. Scientific-psychological and neuroscientific accounts
  • 11.2. Dualism and physicalism
  • 11.3. Wittgenstein and Sartre
  • 11.4. Behaviourism
  • 11.5. Other functionalisms
  • 11.6. Dennett on 'multiple drafts' and 'Joycean machines'
  • 11.7. Pure representationalism
  • 11.8. Higher-order perception
  • 11.9. Higher-order thought
  • 11.10. Core points
  • Bibliography
  • Index